Psychology

© Georges Canguilhem, Trans. David M. Peña-Guzmán 2016 ISSN: 1832-5203 Foucault Studies, No. 21, pp. 200-213, June 2016

TRANSLATION

What is Psychology?* Georges Canguilhem

The psychologist seems to be more embarrassed by the question “What is psychology?” than the philosopher by the question “What is philosophy?” The reason is that philosophy is constituted by the question of its sense and essence much more than it is defined by any answer to it. The fact that this question is reborn incessantly without ever admitting a satisfying response is, for those who would like to call themselves “philosophers,” a reason for humility and not a cause for humiliation. But, for psychology, the question of its essence, or more modestly of its concept, also brings into question the very existence of the psychologist since, lacking the ability to explain what he is, he has difficulty explaining what

* Georges Canguilhem’s “Qu’est-ce que la psychologie?” was first delivered at the Collège Philosophique on December 18, 1956. It was then published in Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale in 1958. Eight years later, in 1966, it appeared in the second volume of the Cahiers pour l’Analyse, which bore its title. This volume included a “Foreword” by Jean-Claude Milner, a “Supplement” (“Les graphes de Jacques Lacan, commentés par Jacques- Alain Miller”), and contributions by Robert Pagès, Alain Grosrichard, Chevalier de Merian, Serge Leclaire, and Thomas Herbert. Translation source: Georges Canguilhem, “Qu’est-ce que la psychologie?” Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale, Vol. 63, No. 1 (January-March, 1958), 12-25. Translator’s note: Translation work is labor-intensive and tiring, on a good day. Here, I have tried to stay as close as possible to the letter of Canguilhem’s text. For example, unlike other translations (in both English and Spanish), this one reproduces all the section- and paragraph-breaks of the original 1958 article. And while works mentioned in the body of the essay are presented here under the title of their English translations (when available), all references have been preserved in their original French (mainly to protect the accuracy of page references). In spite of my largely literalist approach to translation, however, there were moments I was forced to abandon this path. For the sake of readability, for instance, I made some stylistic calls. I changed a few commas to semi-colons and, once or twice, introduced a period. I added quotation marks in places where the mention/use distinction was helpful and appropriate. I relied on dashes and parentheses to break up some the longer and more cumbersome sentences in the original text. I also translated idiomatic expressions in French into idiomatic expressions in English given that a strict attachment to the literal meaning would have resulted in a bizarre, and bizarrely fractured, style entirely foreign to Canguilhem himself. Finally, where translation proved particularly onerous, I opted for presenting the original French alongside the English translation in bracketed form. Special thanks to Rabih Hage, Simon Truwant, and Ellie Anderson for aiding and abetting in this translation.

200

Foucault Studies, No. 21, pp. 200-213.

he does. He can justify his importance as a specialist only by pointing to an always-debatable “efficiency” [efficacité]. And some would not care one bit if this “efficiency” engendered, in the philosopher, an inferiority complex.

In saying of the psychologist’s efficiency that it is debatable, we do not mean that it is illusory; we simply want to note that it will remain, without doubt, ill-founded as long as it has not been shown to be really due to the application of a science, which is to say, as long as the status of psychology is not fixed in such a way that one would be forced to take it for something more and better than a composite empiricism that has been codified, literally, for the sake of teaching. In fact, from a good number of works in psychology one gets the impression that they add up to a philosophy without rigor, an ethics without exigency, and a medicine without control. Philosophy without rigor because it is eclectic under the pretense of objectivity; ethics without exigency because it teams up with ethological experiences that are themselves without critique, e.g. those of the confessor, of the educator, of the leader, of the judge, etc.; and medicine without control because of the three kinds of illnesses most unintelligible and least curable—i.e., illnesses of the skin, illness of the nerves, and mental illnesses—the study and treatment of the last two have always furnished to psychology its observations and hypotheses.

Therefore, it seems that in asking “What is psychology?” one poses a question that is neither impertinent nor futile.

For a long time we have looked for the unity characteristic of the concept of a science in the direction of its object. The object would dictate the method used for the study of its properties. But this was, at bottom, to limit science to the investigation of a fact [un donné], to the exploration of a domain. When it became clear that every science more or less gives itself its fact and appropriates for itself, in this way, what one calls its “domain,” the concept of a science became progressively more focused on its method than on its object. Or more exactly, the expression “object of science” acquired a new sense. The object of science is no longer only the specific domain of problems and obstacles to resolve, it is also the intention and target of the subject of science, it is the specific project that constitutes a theoretical conscience as such. One could respond to the question “What is psychology?” by making appear the unity of its domain in spite of the multiplicity of methodological projects. To this type of response belongs that brilliantly given by Professor Daniel Lagache, in 1947, to a question posed, in 1936, by Édouard Clasparède. 1 The unity of psychology is here sought in its possible definition as general theory of behavior—a synthesis of experimental psychology, clinical psychology, psychoanalysis, social psychology, and ethnology.

1 Édouard Clasparède, L’unite de la pscyhologie (Paris: PUF, 1949).

201

Canguilhem: What is Psychology?

On a closer look, however, we notice that perhaps this unity looks like a pact of peaceful coexistence signed by professionals more than a logical essence obtained by the revelation of constancy across a variety of cases. Of the two tendencies between which Professor Lagache want to find a solid accord—i.e. the naturalist one (experimental psychology) and the humanist (clinical psychology)—, one gets the impression that the second carries, for him, more weight. Without a doubt, this is what explains the absence of animal psychology from this review of disputing parties. True, we see very clearly that it is contained by experimental psychology—which is in large part a psychology of animals—, but it is contained there only as material to which the method is applied. In reality, a psychology can be considered “experimental” only on account of its method, and not on account of its object. Meanwhile, and despite appearances, it is on account of its object more than its method that a psychology is said to be “clinical,” “psychoanalytic,” “social,” “ethnological.” All these adjectives are indicative of one and the same object of study: man, loquacious or taciturn, sociable or unsociable. In light of this, can one rigorously speak about a general theory of behavior as long as the question of whether there is continuity or rupture between human language and animal language, between human and animal society, remains unsolved? It is certainly possible that, on this point, it may not be philosophy that gets to decide, but science, in fact many sciences, psychology included. But in order to define itself, psychology cannot prejudge what it is called upon to judge. Otherwise, it is inevitable that in presenting itself as the general theory of behavior, psychology will incorporate some idea of Man. Hence, it is necessary that we allow philosophy to question psychology about where this idea comes from, and whether it may not be, ultimately, from some philosophy.

Because we are not psychologists, we would like to broach the fundamental question posed here via a different route. That is to say, we propose to explore whether or not the unity of a project can confer to the different types of disciplines called “psychological” their eventual unity. But our method of investigation demands a step back [un recul]. Exploring how various domains overlap can be done by their separate investigation and by comparing them with one another in the present (about a decade in the case of Professor Lagache). Exploring whether certain projects coincide demands that we extract the sense of each of them, not at the moment it gets lost in the automatism of application but at the moment it emerges from the situation that provokes it. Searching for an answer to the question “What is psychology?” becomes, for us, the obligation of sketching a history of psychology, one considered of course solely in relation to its orientations and in connection with the history of philosophy and the history of the sciences; a history necessarily teleological since it is destined to convey to the posed question the assumed original sense of the diverse disciplines, methods, or enterprises whose current disparity legitimizes this same question.

202

Foucault Studies, No. 21, pp. 200-213.

Psychology as natural science Although etymologically “psychology” means science of the soul, it is remarkable that an independent psychology is missing, in both idea and fact, from the philosophical systems of antiquity, where the psyche, or soul, is taken to be a natural being. There, investigations of the soul find themselves split between metaphysics, logic, and physics. The Aristotelian treatise On the Soul is in reality a treatise of general biology, one of his writings consecrated to physics. After Aristotle, and according to the tradition of the School, the “Courses of Philosophy” at the beginning of the 17th century still discuss the soul in the chapter on physics.2 The object of physics is the natural and organized body that has life as a potentiality [ayant la vie en puissance]. Thus, physics treats the soul as the form of the living body and not as a substance separate from matter. From this point of view, a study of the organs of knowledge—that is to say, of the external senses (the five usual senses) and the internal senses (common sense, fantasy, memory)—does not differ in any regard from a study of the organs of respiration or digestion. The soul is a natural object of study, a form in the hierarchy of forms, even if its essential function is the knowledge of forms. The science of the soul is a province of physiology, in its original and universal sense as a theory of nature.

It is to this ancient conception that an aspect of modern psychology returns without interruption: psycho-physiology (for a long time exclusively considered as psycho-neurology but today, also, as psycho-endocrinology) and psycho-pathology (as medical discipline). In this respect, it does not seem superfluous to recall that well before the two revolutions that permitted the development of modern physiology, those of Harvey and Lavoisier, a revolution no less important than those produced by the theory of circulation and respiration was set in motion by Galen when he established, clinically and experimentally—after the doctors of the School of Alexandria (Herophilus and Erasistratus), against Aristotelian doctrine, and in accordance with the anticipations of Alcmaeon, Hippocrates, and Plato—that it is the brain and not the heart that is the organ of sensation and movement, and the seat of the soul. Galen truly founds an uninterrupted filiation of research, an empirical pneumatology for centuries, in which the fundamental piece is the theory of animal spirits, and which was dethroned and superseded at the end of the 18th century by electro-neurology. While decidedly pluralist in his conception of the relationship between the psychic functions and the encephalic organs, Gall proceeds directly from Galen and dominates, in spite of his extravagances, all investigations of cerebral localizations during the first sixty years of the 19th century, until Broca.

In sum, the psychology of today, as psycho-physiology and psycho-pathology, always returns to the 2nd century.

2 Cf. Scipion De Pleix, Corps de Philosophie contenant la Logique, la Physique, la Métaphysique et l’Ethique (Genève, 1636 [1st ed., Paris, 1607]).

203

Canguilhem: What is Psychology?

Psychology as the Science of Subjectivity The decline of Aristotelian physics in the 17th century marks the end of psychology as para- physics, as science of a natural object, and correlatively the birth of psychology as science of subjectivity.

Those truly responsible for the advent of modern psychology as the science of the thinking subject are the mechanical physicists of the 17th century.3

If the reality of the world is not confused with the content of perception, if reality is obtained and posed vis-à-vis the reduction of illusions of sensible experience, then the qualitative residue of this experience engages, in virtue of being possible as falsification of the real, the responsibility of spirit, which is to say, of the subject of experience insofar as it does not identify itself with mathematical or mechanical reason, instrument of truth and measure of reality.

But this responsibility is, to the eyes of the physicist, culpability. Psychology constitutes itself as the enterprise for the exoneration of spirit. Its project is that of a science that, in the face of physics, explains why spirit is forced by nature, first and foremost, to trick reason with respect to reality. Psychology becomes a physics of external sense in order to account for the counter-senses that mechanical physics imputes to the use of the senses in the function of knowledge.

The Physics of External Sense Psychology, the science of subjectivity, begins as psychophysics for two reasons. First, because it cannot be less than a physics if it is to be taken seriously by physicists. Second, because it must look in a certain nature—i.e., in the structure of the human body—for the reason for the existence of the irreal residues [résidus irréels] of human experience.

But even so, this is not a return to the ancient conception of a science of the soul, a branch of physics. The new physics is a calculus. Psychology tends to imitate it. It will seek to determine the quantitative constants of sensation and the relations between these constants.

Here, Descartes and Malebranche are the leaders. In Rules for the Direction of the Mind (XII), Descartes proposes the reduction of qualitative differences between sense data to a difference between geometric figures. Here, it is a matter of sense data insofar as they are, in the proper sense of the term, information from one body to others. And what is informed by the external senses is an internal sense: “fantasy, which is nothing more than a real and figured body.” In Rule XIV, Descartes expressly deals with what Kant will call the intensive magnitude of sensations (Critique of Pure Reason, transcendental analytic, anticipation of perception): the comparisons between lights, sounds, etc., which cannot be converted into

3 Cf. Aron Gurwitsch, Déveleoppement historique de la Gestalt-Osychologie, in Thalès, 2nd year (1935), 167-175.

204

Foucault Studies, No. 21, pp. 200-213.

exact reports except by analogy with the extension of the figured body. If we add that Descartes, even if not properly speaking the inventor of the term and concept of the reflex, has nonetheless affirmed the constancy of the link between excitation and reaction, we see that psychology—understood as the mathematical physics of external sense—begins with him and culminates with Fechner, thanks to the help of physiologists such as Hermann Helmholtz, and in spite of and against the Kantian reserves criticized, in turn, by Herbart.

This type of psychology is enlarged to the dimensions of an experimental psychology by Wundt, whose is motivated by the hope of making appear, in the laws of the “facts of consciousness,” the same kind of analytical determinism that mechanics and physics expect from any universally valid science.

Fechner died in 1887, two years before Bergson’s thesis, Time and Free Will: An Essay on the Immediate Data of Consciousness (1889). Wundt died in 1920 having formed a good amount of disciples (some of whom are still alive), and not without having contributed to the first attacks launched by the psychologists of Form against the analytical physics (at once experimental and mathematical) of external sense. This was done in accordance with Ehrenfels’ observations about the qualities of form (On the Qualities of Form, 1890), which themselves resemble Bergson’s analysis of totalities perceived as organic forms that dominate their supposed parts (Time and Free Will, ch. II).

The science of internal sense But the science of subjectivity does not reduce to the elaboration of a physics of external sense. It suggests and presents itself as the science of self-consciousness or the science of internal sense. The term psychology dates to the 18th century, having the sense of the science of the “I” (Wolff). The entire history of this psychology can be written as the history of the counter-senses [des contre-sens] that the Meditations of Descartes initiate without, however, assuming responsibility for doing so.

When Descartes, at the start of Meditation III, considers his “interior” to render himself better known and more familiar to himself, the consideration aims at Thinking. The Cartesian interior, consciousness of the Ego cogito, is the direct knowledge the soul has of itself qua pure understanding. Descartes calls the Meditations “metaphysical” because they claim to arrive directly at the nature and essence of the “I think” in the immediate grasping of its existence. Cartesian meditation is not a personal confessional [une confidence personnelle]. The reflection that gives self-knowledge the rigor and impersonality of mathematics is not the kind of self- observation that the spiritualists will to trace back to Socrates beginning in the 19th century, so that Mr. Pierre-Paul Royer-Collard can give Napoleon I the assurance that the Know Thyself, the Cogito, and Introspection all give the throne and the altar their impregnable foundation.

205

Canguilhem: What is Psychology?

The Cartesian interior has nothing in common with the internal sense of the Aristotelians, “who conceive their objects interiorly and inside the head,” 4 and which Descartes considered, as we have seen, as an aspect of the body (Rule XIII). This is why Descartes says that the soul knows itself directly and more easily than the body. We overlook the explicitly polemical intention of this affirmation too often because, according to Aristotelians, the soul does not know itself directly. “Knowledge of the soul is not direct, but only by reflection. This is because the soul is similar to the eye that sees everything but cannot see itself except by reflection as in a mirror […] and the soul, by parallel, does not see itself and does not know itself except by reflection and recognition of its effects.”5 This thesis rouses the indignation of Descartes when Gassendi reclaims it in his objections to Meditation III, and to which he responds: “It is not the eye that sees itself, or the mirror, but spirit, which alone knows the mirror, the eye, and itself.”

But this decisive reply does not put an end to this scholastic argument. Maine de Biran uses it once more against Descartes in “On the Decomposition of Thought,” and A. Comte invokes it against the possibility of introspection, that is to say, against the method of self- knowledge that Reid borrows from Pierre-Paul Royer-Collard to turn psychology into the scientific propaedeutic to metaphysics, thus justifying by experimental means the traditional theses of spiritualist substantialism.6 Even Cournot, in all his wisdom, does not hold back from also taking up this argument, this time to support the idea that psychological observation concerns the behavior of others more than the “I” of the observer, that psychology resembles wisdom more than science, and that “it is in the nature of psychological facts to be translated into aphorisms rather than theorems.”7

One has misunderstood the teachings of Descartes if one constitutes, against him, empirical psychology as the natural history of the “I”—from Locke to Ribot, passing through Condillac, the French Ideologues and the English Utilitarians—or if one constitutes, after him, a rational psychology founded on the intuition of a substantial “I.”

To Kant still belongs the glory of having established that even if Wolff was able to baptize his post-Cartesian newborns (Psychologia empirica, 1732; Psychologia rationalis, 1734), he was nonetheless unable to successfully found their pretensions to legitimacy. Kant shows, on the one hand, that phenomenal internal sense is just a form of empirical intuition, which he tends to confuse with time. On the other, he shows that the “I” that is the subject of all judgment of apperception is itself a function of the organization of experience, but one of which there can be no science because it is the transcendental condition for all science. The Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science (1786) challenges the scientific scope of psychology,

4 Scipion Du Pleix, op. cit., Physique, 439. 5 Ibid., 353. 6 Cours de Philosophie positive, 1re leçon. 7 Cournot, Essai sur le fondements de nos connaissance (1851), §§371-376.

206

Foucault Studies, No. 21, pp. 200-213.

whether based on the image of mathematics or physics. No mathematical psychology is possible in the same way that there exists a mathematical physics. Even if one, in virtue of anticipating perception relative to intensive magnitudes, applied the mathematics of the continuous to the modifications of internal sense, one would not thereby obtain anything more than a geometry confined to the study of the properties of the straight line. There is also no experimental psychology in the same way that there is a chemistry that constitutes itself by the use of analysis and synthesis. We cannot experiment on others or ourselves. Plus, internal observation affects its object. Wanting to surprise oneself in self-observation would lead to insanity [alienation]. Psychology, then, can only be descriptive. Its true place is in an Anthropology, as a propaedeutic to a theory of skill and prudence, crowned by a theory of wisdom.

The science of intimate sense If we call “classical psychology” what we intent to refute, it must be noted that in psychology there are always classics for someone. The Ideologues, heirs to the sensualists, took as “classical” the Scottish psychology that only advocated, like them, an inductive method so as to better affirm, against them, the substantiality of spirit. And, before being rejected as “classical” by the theoreticians of Gestalt psychology, the atomistic and analytic psychology of the sensualists and the Ideologues was itself already viewed as such by a romantic psychologist like Maine de Biran. Through him, psychology becomes the technique of the Diary and the science of intimate sense. The solitude of Descartes was the asceticism of a mathematician. The solitude of Maine de Biran is the idleness of a school principal. The Cartesian I think founds thought itself. The Biranian I want founds self-consciousness over and against an exteriority. At his isolated desk, Biran discovers that psychological analysis does not consist in simplifying but in complicating; that the primitive psychic fact is not an element but already a relation, and that this relation is lived with effort. He arrives at two conclusions, unexpected for a man whose functions are of authority, which is to say, commandment: consciousness requires the conflict between a power and a resistance; man is not, as de Bonald thought, an intelligence serviced by the organs but a living organization serviced by intelligence. It is necessary for the soul to be incarnated, and so there can be no psychology without biology. Self-observation does not forgo recourse to either the physiology of voluntary movement or the pathology of affectivity. The situation of Maine de Biran is unique, between the two Royer-Collards. He has dialogued with the doctrinarian and been judged by the psychiatrist. We have from Maine de Biran a “Promenade avec M. Royer- Collard dans les jardins du Luxembourg” and we have from Antoine-Athanase Royer- Collard, the former’s younger brother, an “Examen de la Doctrine de Maine de Biran.”8 If

8 Published by his son Hyacinthe Royer-Collard (in Annales Médico-Psychologiques, Book 2 (1843), 1).

207

Canguilhem: What is Psychology?

Maine de Biran had not read and discussed Cabanis (On the Relations between the Physical and Moral Aspects in Man, 1798), if he had not read and discussed Bichat (Physiological Researches on Life and Death, 1800), the history of pathological psychology would ignore him, which it cannot do. The second Royer-Collard is, after Pinel and alongside Esquirol, one of the founders of the French school of psychiatry. Pinel had pleaded for the idea that the insane are at once sick patients like the rest, neither possessed nor criminals, and also different from them and should be cared for separately and separated, depending on the case, into specialized hospital services. Pinel founded mental medicine as an independent discipline, starting from the therapeutic isolation of the insane at Bicêtre and Salpêtrière. Royer-Collard imitates Pinel at the Maison Nationale de Charenton, where he becomes head doctor in 1805, the same year Esquirol defends his medical thesis on The Passions Considered as Causes, Symptoms and Means of Cure in Cases of Insanity. Royer-Collard becomes, in 1816, professor of legal medicine at the Faculty of Medicine of Paris and, in 1821, the first holder of the chair of mental medicine. Royer-Collard and Esquirol had as pupils: Calmeil, who studied paralysis in the insane; Bayle, who recognized and isolated general paralysis; Félix Voisin, who created the study of mental retardation in infants. And it is at Salpêtrière that—after Pinel, Esquirol, Lelut, Baillarger, and Falret, among others—Charcot becomes, in 1862, the leader of a service whose works will be followed by Théodule Ribot, Pierre Janet, cardinal Mercier, and Sigmund Freud.

We have seen psycho-pathology positively begin with Galen and culminate in Sigmund Freud, creator of the term “psychoanalysis” in 1896. Psycho-pathology did not develop in isolation from the other psychological disciplines. Because of the investigations of Biran, it compelled philosophy to ask itself, since at least a century before, from which of the two Royer-Collards it should borrow the idea of psychology that we must develop. In this way, psycho-pathology is at once judge and party to that uninterrupted debate in which metaphysics gives direction to psychology without thereby giving up the right to say a word about the relationship between the physical and the psychic. For a long time, this relationship has been formulated as somato-physical before becoming psycho-somatic. This reversal is the same, moreover, as the one carried out on the signification of the unconscious. If one identifies psychism and consciousness—based, rightly or wrongly, on the authority of Descartes—, the unconscious turns out to be of a physical order. If one assumes that the psychic can be unconscious, psychology does not reduce to the science of consciousness. And the psychic is no longer only what is hidden, but also what hides itself, that which one hides; it is not simply the intimate, but also—a term Bossuet takes from the mystics—the abyssal. Psychology is no longer just the science of intimacy, but the science of the profundities of the soul.

208

Foucault Studies, No. 21, pp. 200-213.

Psychology as science of reactions and of behavior In proposing to define Man [l’homme] as a living organization serviced by intelligence, Maine de Biran marked in advance—better, apparently, than Gall who thought, according to Lelut, that “man is no longer an intelligence but a will serviced by the organs”9—the terrain on which a new psychology would be constituted in the 19th century. But, at the same time, he assigned it its limits since, in his Anthropology, he situated human life between animal and spiritual life.

The 19th century sees the biology of human behavior emerge (alongside psychology) as a nervous and mental pathology, as the physics of external sense, as the science of internal and intimate sense. The reasons for this emergence seem to be the following. First, scientific reasons to know: the constitution of Biology as a general theory of the relations between organisms and their milieus, which marks the end of belief in the existence of a separate human reign. Then, technical and economic reasons to know: the development of an industrial regime that directs attention to the industrious character of the human species and marks the end of belief in the dignity of speculative thought. And, finally, political reasons that mark the end of belief in values of social privilege and result in the diffusion of egalitarianism: conscription and public education become State affairs, and the demand for equality in military positions and civil functions (to each according to his job, works, or merits) becomes the real, though often overlooked, foundation of a phenomenon proper to modern societies, that is to say, the generalized practice of expertise, in every sense of the word, as the determination of competence and the test for simulation.

At any rate, what characterizes this psychology of behavior, in comparison to other types of psychological investigation, is its constitutional incapacity to grasp and present with clarity its founding project. If among the founding projects of previous types of psychology, there are some that pass for philosophical counter-senses [des contre-sens philosophiques], here, to the contrary—all links to philosophical theory having been refused—the issue is to figure out from where a given psychological investigation gets its sense. In accepting to become, under the sponsorship of biology, an objective science of aptitudes, reactions, and behaviors, psychology and psychologists completely forget to situate their own specific behaviors in the context of their historical circumstances and the social milieus in which they propose their methods or techniques, and in which they make their services accepted.

Nietzsche, adumbrating the psychology of the 19th century psychologist, writes: “We, psychologists of the future, view the instrument that wishes to know itself almost as a sign of degeneration; we are the instruments of knowledge and we would like to have all the naïveté and precision of an instrument; so we must not analyze ourselves, know ourselves.” 10

9 Qu’est-ce que la phrénologie? Ou Essai sur la signification et la valeur des systèmes de psychologie en général et de celui de Gall, en particulier, (Paris, 1836), 401. 10 Nietzsche, La volonté de puissance, translated by Bianquis, Book 3, §335.

209

Canguilhem: What is Psychology?

Astonishing misunderstanding, and how revealing too! The psychologist only wants to be an instrument, without knowing of what or of whom. Nietzsche seemed more inspired when, at the start of The Genealogy of Morality, he applied himself to the enigma represented by English psychologists, that is to say, the utilitarians who were preoccupied with the genesis of moral sentiments. He wondered what had pushed them in the direction of cynicism when explaining human behavior in terms of interest and utility, and in the direction of forgetting these fundamental motivations. It is precisely here that, in the face of the behavior of the psychologists of the 19th century, Nietzsche provisionally renounces all cynicism, which is to say, all lucidity!

The idea of utility, as a principle of psychology, is linked to the philosophical understanding of human nature as a power of artifice [comme puissance d’artifice] (Hume, Burke) or, more prosaically, to the definition of Man as a toolmaker (the French Encyclopédistes, Adam Smith, Franklin). But the principle of a biological psychology of behavior does not seem to have been disengaged, in the same fashion, from an explicitly philosophical conscience, without a doubt because this principle can be activated only on the condition that it remain unformulated. This principle is the definition of Man himself as tool. Utilitarianism (which implicates the idea of utility for man, the idea of Man as judge of utility) was succeeded by instrumentalism (which implicates the idea of the utility of man, the idea of Man as mean to utility). Intelligence is no longer what organizes the organs and avails itself of them, but what services them. And it is not with impunity that the historical origins of the psychology of reaction must be sought in the works produced by the discovery of “the personal equation” of astronomers using the telescope (Maskelyne, 1796). Man was studied first as the instrument of the scientific instrument, before being studied as the instrument of all instruments.

The investigations of the laws of adaptation and learning, of the detection and measurement of aptitudes, and of the conditions of output and productivity (whether concerning individuals or groups)—investigations that are inseparable from their applications to selection or orientation—admit a common implicit postulate: the nature of Man is to be a tool, and his vocation is to be put in his place, to his task.

Nietzsche, of course, is right to say that the psychologists would like to be the “naïve and precise instruments” of this study of man. They have struggled to reach objective knowledge, even if the determinism they seek in behavior is no longer the sort of Newtonian determinism familiar to the first physicists of the 19th century, but rather a statistical determinism, progressively resting on the findings of biometrics. But what is the sense of this instrumentalism to the second power? What is it that pushes or inclines psychologists to appoint themselves, of all men, the instruments of an ambition to treat Man as an instrument? In the other types of psychology, the soul or the subject—as natural form or consciousness of interiority—is the principle used to justify the value a certain idea of Man

210

Foucault Studies, No. 21, pp. 200-213.

relative to the truth of things. But for a psychology in which the word “soul” causes flight and the word “consciousness” laughter, the truth of Man is captured by the fact that there is no longer any idea of Man as anything other than a tool. We must recognize that to talk about the idea of a tool, it is necessary that not every idea belong to the rank of a tool; and that in order to assign a value to a tool, it is precisely necessary that not every value be that of a tool whose subordinate value consists in procuring some other thing. Now, if the psychologist cannot derive his psychological project from an idea of man, does he think he can justify this project with his behavior of the utilization of man? We say it well, “his behavior of utilization,” in spite of two possible objections. Someone could say that, in a way, this type of psychology does not ignore the distinction between theory and application and, in another way, that this utilization is not ultimately the doing of the psychologist himself but of the person or persons who ask him for reports and diagnostics. We will respond that, unless one is going to confuse the theoretician of psychology with the professor of psychology, one must recognize that the contemporary psychologist is, more often than not, a practicing professional whose “science” is completely motivated by that search for “laws” of adaptation to a socio-technological environment—not to a natural environment—, for that which confers on his operations of “measure” a signification of evaluation and a range of expertise. In this way the behavior of the psychologist of human behavior involves, almost by necessity, a feeling of superiority, a good dirigist conscience, the mentality of a manager of the relations between man and man. That is why we must go back to the cynical question: who designates psychologists as the instruments of instrumentalism? How do we recognize those men who are worthy of assigning to instrument-man [l’homme-instrument] his role and function? Who counsels the counselors?

Needless to say, we do not place ourselves on the terrain of capacities and technique. Whether there are good or bad psychologists—that is to say, technicians skilled due to learning and technicians noxious due to stupidity not forbidden by law—is not the issue. The issue is that a science or a scientific technique do not contain, within themselves, any idea that could confer them their sense. In his Introduction to Psychology, Paul Guillaume described the psychology of a man taking a test. The subject [le testé] defends himself against this investigation, fearing that an action is being exercise over it. Guillaume sees in this state of mind an acknowledgement of the efficacy of the test. But one could also see here the embryo of the psychology of the tester. The defense of the subject being tested is the repugnance of seeing itself treated like an insect by a man who is not recognized as having the authority to tell him what he is or what he must do. “To treat like an insect,” the word is from Stendhal, who

211

Canguilhem: What is Psychology?

takes it from Cuvier.11 What if we treated the psychologist like an insect? What if we applied to the dismal and insipid Kinsey, for example, Stendhal’s recommendation?

In other words, in 19th and 20th centuries, the psychology of reaction and behavior thought it made itself independent by separating itself form all philosophy, that is to say, from the kind of speculation that looks for an idea of Man beyond the biological and sociological facts. But this psychology could not prevent the recurrence of its results in the behavior of those who obtain them. And, to the extend that one forbids philosophy from furnishing the answer, the question “What is psychology?” becomes “In doing what they do, what do psychologists hope to accomplish?” “In the name of what are they instituted psychologists?” When Gideon takes command as the head of the Israelites and escorts the Midianites beyond the Jordan (The Bible: Judges, Book VII), he uses a test of two degrees that permits him to keep only ten thousand out of thirty-two thousand men, and then three hundred out of ten thousand. But this test owes to the Eternal the finalization of its use and the process of selection used. To select a selector, it is normally necessary to transcend the blueprint of technical selection procedures. In the immanence of scientific psychology, the question remains: Who has, not the competence, but the mission of being a psychologist? Psychology always relies on an doubling up [dédoublement], but this is no longer the doubling of consciousness (according to the facts and norms entailed by the idea of man); it is the doubling of a mass of “subjects” and of an elite corporation of specialists who invest themselves with their proper mission.

In Kant and Maine de Biran, psychology situates itself in an Anthropology, which is to say—despite the ambiguity, much in vogue today, of this term—in a philosophy. In Kant, the general theory of human ability is still connected to a theory of wisdom [sagesse]. Instrumental psychology presents itself as a general theory of ability outside any reference to wisdom. If we cannot define this psychology via an idea of man, that is to say, if we cannot situate psychology within philosophy, we do not have the power to prevent anyone from just considering themselves “psychologists” and calling whatever they do “psychology.” But neither can we prevent philosophy from continuing to interrogate the ill-defined status of psychology, ill-defined from the viewpoint of the sciences as much as from that of techniques. In doing this, philosophy carries itself with a constitutive ingenuity that is so different from gullibility that it does not exclude a provisional cynicism. This ingenuity leads philosophy to return, once again, to the common sector, to the side of non-specialists.

It is rather vulgarly, then, that philosophy poses to psychology the question: tell me what you aim for so that I may find out what you are? But a philosopher can also address

11 “Instead of hating the small bookseller of the neighboring town who sells the Popular Almanac, I used to say to my friend Mr. de Ranville to apply to him the remedy indicated by Cuvier: treat him like an insect. Find out what are his means of sustenance, try to guess his ways of making love” (Stendhal, Mémoires d’un Touriste, Calmann-Lévy (ed.), Book 2, page 23).

212

Foucault Studies, No. 21, pp. 200-213.

himself to the psychologist in the form of offering orientation advice (one time does not a habit make!), and say to him: when one leaves the Sorbonne by the street Saint-Jacques, one can ascend or descend; if one ascends, one approaches the Pantheon, the conservatory of great men; but if one descends, one heads directly to the Police Department.

Georges Canguilhem Transl

Advertisements

Habermas and Pragmatism

Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2004.03.07,
Aboulafia, Mitchell, Myra Bookman, and Catherine Kemp (eds.), Habermas and Pragmatism, Routledge, 2002, 256pp.
Reviewed by Christopher F. Zurn, University of Kentucky
(Excerpts)
This volume is a well-conceived and important new addition to the secondary literature on the wide-ranging philosophical work of Jürgen Habermas. …
…The volume is capped by the short three-part “Postscript: Some Concluding Remarks” by Habermas, consisting of, first, a “Response” that acknowledges his debt to the contributors and briefly responds to specific criticisms presented in the volume by Apel and Michelman, second “Reflections on Pragmatism” in the form of responses to six questions posed by Aboulafia to Habermas concerning his relationship to the work of the American pragmatists, and third a short, previously untranslated Die Zeit piece from 1998 “On John Dewey’s Quest for Certainty.”
In this “Postscript,” Aboulafia receives Habermas’s pithiest response to the question “What are the greatest strengths of pragmatism?”: “The combination of fallibilism with anti-skepticism, and a naturalist approach to the human mind and its culture that refuses to yield to any kind of scientism” (p. 228). Of course, we can read this claim not only as a relatively dispassionate assessment of the history of philosophical movements, but also as a self-attribution of what Habermas himself hopes to have achieved in his work by drawing on specific pragmatist insights and philosophical strategies.
Stylizing somewhat, we might even speculate that Habermas aims for a measure of anti-skeptical fallibilism in his methodological and epistemological projects by drawing on C. S. Peirce’s attempt to save the cognitive content of the Kantian ideas of reason without recourse, however, to a metaphysical appeal to the noumenal realm. Perhaps he hopes to have achieved an anti-scientistic—let us say, anti-reductivist—but nevertheless naturalistic theory of human culture and subjectivity by drawing on G. H. Mead’s account of human ontogenesis and phylogenesis in terms of universal structures developed through intersubjective symbolic interaction. The strategy that Habermas shares with Peirce is two-fold: on the one hand, an empirical, hence fallibilistic, appeal to the unavoidable presuppositions built into the everyday use of language, and, on the other hand, an idealizing, hence anti-skeptical, appeal to the meaning of epistemic presuppositions in terms of an asymptotic progress towards truth and objectivity as achieved by an unlimited community of problem-solving interlocutors. The strategy that Habermas shares with Mead is also two-fold: on the one-hand, an appeal to the best contemporary naturalistic accounts of individual and socio-cultural development in terms of the irreducibly intersubjective structures of language use, without, on the other hand, supposing that one could simply ignore the normativity of such developmental structures through a positivistic reduction of the problems of the social sciences and philosophy to the results of the so-called ’hard’ sciences and thereby sidestep the difficult hermeneutic issues raised by the linguistic milieu of the structures.
Of course, realizing such aspirations towards an anti-skeptical fallibilism and an anti-reductivist naturalism involves one in a sort of philosophical high-wire act, finding just the right path between the dead-ends of dogmatism and skepticism, between over-confident rationalism and a dismissal of philosophy as passé. This volume attests to both the interest and the precariousness of that balance through a compelling series of essays which add weight to one or another side in their respective attempts to show the unsustainable character of Habermas’s theoretical equilibrium.
Contemporary English-language philosophers who sail under the banner of pragmatism are, of course, somewhat more skeptical than Habermas about the possibilities for any non-metaphysical, naturalistic, and fully fallibilistic account—no matter how ’detranscendentalized’—of Kantian and post-Kantian ideas of reason such as unconditional truth, objectivity, rational accountability, freedom, normativity, linguistic universals, context-transcendent justification, and so on. …
… By bringing Habermas’s work into explicit conversation with both historical and contemporary forms of philosophical pragmatism, Aboulafia, Bookman and Kemp have put together a book that will be of service to specialists and those new to the field alike. It should also provoke further debates about the tenability of Habermas’s pragmatist-inspired high-wire act, balancing between fallibilism and skepticism, as well as between naturalism and reductivism.

Personnalisme

From: Wikipédia

Naissance du personnalisme avant 1930

Le terme personnalisme a été inventé par un pasteur de l’Église réformée, Albin Mazel, dans le cadre d’une étude intitulée « Solidarisme, individualisme et socialisme ». Le terme a été repris ensuite par Charles Renouvier dans une optique kantienne en 19033. Kant pourrait donc passer pour le vrai fondateur du personnalisme. En effet, Kant, en mettant le sujet au centre de l’expérience en général, et de l’expérience morale en particulier, met en pleine lumière la personne capable d’être à elle-même sa propre fin. La philosophie personnaliste doit aussi beaucoup à Nicolas Berdiaev, philosophe orthodoxe russe arrivé à Paris en 1924 avec lequel Mounier collabore dès les premiers numéro d’Esprit. Mounier lui emprunte le concept de personnalisme communautaire et son insistance sur la liberté et la créativité comme fondement de la personne, comme fondement de la spiritualité.

Le Personnalisme au cours des années 1930

À partir des années 1930, le personnalisme est devenu un mouvement intellectuel de réaction à la crise économique profonde de cette décennie, que la jeunesse intellectuelle française percevait comme une crise de civilisation plutôt que comme une crise essentiellement économique. Cette crise, ces jeunes la caractérisent en opposant l’« individu » et la « personne », opposition empruntée d’ailleurs à Charles Péguy, pour manifester leur refus de l’ordre établi exacerbé par la crise économique mondiale qui sévit. Daniel-Rops écrira à ce propos :

  • « Est-il besoin de répéter […] que la personne n’a rien de commun avec l’être schématique mû par des passions élémentaires et sordides, qu’est l’individu. Un personnalisme conscient s’oppose même à l’individualisme dont s’est grisé le XIXe siècle. La personne, c’est l’être tout entier, chair et âme, l’une de l’autre responsable, et tendant au total accomplissement »4.

L’individu, c’est ce qui, en bout de piste, apparaît comme le rejeton des tendances aliénantes du monde moderne. C’est celui qui a sacrifié sa dimension spirituelle et son potentiel d’énergies créatrices et de liberté, au profit d’un idéal petit-bourgeois qui ne vise qu’au bien-être. Pour Emmanuel Mounier : « l’individu, c’est la dissolution de la personne dans la matière. […] Dispersion, avarice, voilà les deux marques de l’individualité. » Aussi, la personne ne peut croître « qu’en se purifiant de l’individu qui est en elle. »5.

Autant la notion d’individu veut exprimer la faillite de la société occidentale que met en relief la crise économique des années 1930, autant celle de personne renferme «comme une absence, un besoin, une tâche et une tension continuellement créatrice»6. Contre le gigantisme des mécanismes sociaux, politiques et économiques qui président aux destinées des hommes ; contre l’idéalisme et le rationalisme abstraits qui ont détaché l’homme de la nature et de ses communautés immédiates, tous les mouvements de la jeunesse française se rejoignent en une même aspiration : celle de renouer avec ce qu’ils appellent l’homme « concret » pour en faire un être responsable, c’est-à-dire capable «de réponse»7.

Cette opposition entre individu et personne, assez répandue au début des années 1930, est donc à la fois un jugement sur la situation et un projet pour la modifier. Ce projet pourrait se formuler de la manière suivante. Le bourgeois, cet être incapable d’élévation spirituelle a, par ses visées égoïstes, inversé l’ordre des valeurs mettant ainsi en péril les possibilités d’épanouissement de la personne et de la civilisation occidentale. Pour mettre un terme à la crise de notre civilisation, la transformation des structures sociales et économiques doit inévitablement s’accompagner d’une révolution spirituelle. Dès 1927, Jacques Maritain soutenait cette Primauté du spirituel. À sa suite, des revues comme la Jeune Droite, l’Ordre Nouveau et Esprit reprendront cette exigence. Ainsi, en mars 1931, l’un des premiers manifestes de l’Ordre Nouveau lançait ce slogan promis à un succès durable: «Spirituel d’abord, économique, ensuite, politique à leur service». Emmanuel Mounier écrira quelque temps plus tard : « Le spirituel commande le politique et l’économique. L’esprit doit garder l’initiative et la maîtrise de ses buts, qui vont à l’homme par-dessus l’homme, et non au bien-être. »8.

Selon ces jeunes intellectuels français, redonner la «primauté à la personne», c’est retrouver la voie de la vraie hiérarchie des valeurs; c’est réunir ce que le monde moderne a eu tendance à séparer. Cette volonté est surtout le souci de la revue Esprit et, dans une moindre mesure, celui de l’Ordre nouveau, revues qui possèdent quelques collaborateurs communs. Toutefois, puisqu’il n’est personne pour croire que cette nouvelle civilisation s’édifiera seulement à coup d’idéal, on a aussi pensé à organiser ce qui relève du matériel sur une base concrète qui puisse permettre d’atteindre la réalisation de cet objectif. Il faut savoir que pour cette génération, Proudhon sera, en ce qui a trait à l’organisation de la dimension matérielle, ce que Charles Péguy représenta pour la dimension spirituelle. Esprit, qui est avant tout Emmanuel Mounier, approfondira surtout la réalité de la personne alors que l’Ordre Nouveau s’attachera plutôt, en s’inspirant plus directement de Proudhon, à définir le cadre organisationnel qui va permettre à l’humanité nouvelle d’émerger.

Herodotus on corruption

From Book V.

“Milesian stranger, quit Sparta before sunset. This is no good proposal that thou makest to the Lacedaemonians, to conduct them a distance of three months’ journey from the sea.” When he had thus spoken, Cleomenes went to his home.

But Aristagoras took an olive-bough in his hand, and hastened to the king’s house, where he was admitted by reason of his suppliant’s pliant’s guise. Gorgo, the daughter of Cleomenes, and his only child, a girl of about eight or nine years of age, happened to be there, standing by her father’s side. Aristagoras, seeing her, requested Cleomenes to send her out of the room before he began to speak with him; but Cleomenes told him to say on, and not mind the child. So Aristagoras began with a promise of ten talents if the king would grant him his request, and when Cleomenes shook his head, continued to raise his offer till it reached fifty talents; whereupon the child spoke:- “Father,” she said, “get up and go, or the stranger will certainly corrupt thee.” Then Cleomenes, pleased at the warning of his child, withdrew and went into another room.

These same men, if we may believe the Athenians, during their stay at Delphi persuaded the Pythoness by a bribe to tell the Spartans, whenever any of them came to consult the oracle, either on their own private affairs or on the business of the state, that they must free Athens. So the Lacedaemonians, when they found no answer ever returned to them but this, sent at last Anchimolius, the son of Aster- a man of note among their citizens- at the head of an army against Athens, with orders to drive out the Pisistratidae, albeit they were bound to them by the closest ties of friendship. For they esteemed the things of heaven more highly than the things of men.

Heidegger és Hegel Semmije

MARTIN HEIDEGGER (1889-1976): MI A METAFIZIKA? (1929)

(részletek)

Kulcsszavak: egzisztencia*, szorongás, önmegértés, tudományfilozófia

Jelenvalólétünket – a kutatók, tanárok és tanulmányaikat folytatók közösségében – a tudomány határozza meg. Minden tudományban, amikor annak legsajátabb célját követjük, magához a létezőhöz viszonyulunk. Ez a létezőre irányuló kitüntetett világvonatkozás az emberi egzisztencia szabadon választott magatartásán nyugszik, ez a magatartás vezérli. Persze, az ember tudomány előtti és tudományon kívüli cselekvése és viselkedése is a létezőhöz viszonyul. A tudomány abban tűnik ki, hogy sajátos módon kifejezetten és egyedül magát a dolgot engedi szóhoz jutni.

Csak a létezőt kell kutatni és – semmi mást; egyedül a létezőt és – semmi egyebet; csakis a létezőt és rajta kívül – semmit. Hogyan is áll a dolog ezzel a Semmivel? A Semmit a tudomány kifejezetten elutasítja és feladja mint semmis-jelentéktelent. Csakhogy: nem éppen akkor ismerjük-e el a Semmit, amikor így feladjuk? A tudomány semmit sem akar tudni a Semmiről. De ugyanilyen biztos ez is: ott, ahol a tudomány kísérletet tesz rá, hogy megfogalmazza a maga lényegét, a Semmit hívja segítségül. Azt veszi igénybe, amit elvet. Miféle meghasonlott lényeg lepleződik itt le? Amikor pillanatnyi egzisztenciánkon – amelyet a tudomány határoz meg – elmélkedünk, egy összeütközés kellős közepébe jutunk. Ez a vita már elindított egy kérdezést. Most már csak arra van szükség, hogy a kérdést megfogalmazzuk: hogyan áll a dolog a Semmivel?

Már az első nekifutás a kérdésnek valami szokatlant mutat. Ebben a kérdezésben eleve úgy tesszük fel a Semmit, mint valamit, ami így és így „van” – mint létezőt. Csakhogy pontosan a létező az, amitől a Semmi teljességgel különbözik. Ennek megfelelően eleve nem lehetséges semmiféle válasz a kérdésre. Hiszen a válasz szükségképpen ilyen formájú: a Semmi ez és ez („van”)*. A Semmit illetően kérdés és felelet egyformán értelmetlen. A gondolkodás rendszerint felemlegetett alapszabálya, az elkerülendő ellentmondás tétele, az általános „logika” elveti a kérdést. Mert a gondolkodás, amely mindig valamiről való gondolkodás, a Semmiről való gondolkodásként saját lényege ellen kellene hogy cselekedjék. De vajon kikezdhetjük-e a „logika” uralmát? Vajon nem az értelem-e az úr a Semmire vonatkozó kérdésben?

Hiszen egyáltalában csak az ő segítségével tudjuk a Semmit meghatározni és mint problémát

megközelíteni, még ha e probléma fel is emészti önmagát. Mert a Semmi a létező mindenségének tagadása, az éppenséggel nem-létező. A tagadás azonban a „logika” uralkodó és kikezdhetetlen tanítása szerint egy sajátos értelmi tevékenység. Csak azért van a Semmi, mert van a Nem, azaz a tagadás? Vagy fordítva áll a helyzet? Csak azért van a tagadás és a Nem, mert a Semmi van? Ez nincsen eldöntve, sőt, kifejezett kérdésként sem fogalmazódott még meg. Mi azt állítottuk: a Semmi eredendőbb, mint a Nem és a tagadás. Ha ez az állítás helyes, akkor a tagadásnak mint értelmi tevékenységnek a lehetősége s ezzel maga az értelem is valamilyen módon a Semmitől függ. Hogy is akarhat akkor az értelem a Semmi felől dönteni?

Talán csak az derül ki a végén, hogy a Semmire vonatkozó kérdés és válasz látszólagos értelmetlensége a – 67 – nyughatatlan értelem vak csökönyösségén nyugszik? A Semmi a létező mindenségének teljes tagadása. Vajon a Semminek ez a jellemzése nem mutat-e végül is olyan irányba, amelyből és csakis ebből utunkba kerülhet? Ahhoz, hogy mint olyan teljességgel tagadhatóvá váljék a létező mindensége, mely tagadásban azután maga a Semmi megmutatkozhatnék, a létező mindenségének előzőleg adottnak kell lennie.

Amilyen biztos az, hogy a létező egészét önmagában soha abszolút módon nem ragadhatjuk meg, olyan bizonyos az is, hogy valahogyan mégiscsak a maga egészében lelepleződött létezőbe állítottan lelünk önmagunkra. A hangoltság, melyben valaki így vagy úgy „van”, lehetővé teszi, hogy általa áthangolva az egészben vett létezőben tartózkodjunk. A hangulatnak ez a diszpozíciója* nemcsak hogy a maga módján minden esetben leleplezi az egészében vett létezőt, hanem egyszersmind ez a leleplezés jelenvalólétünk* alaptörténése. Amit ily módon „érzéseknek” nevezünk, az nem egyszerűen gondolkodó és akaró magatartásunk futólagos kísérő jelensége.

Csakhogy éppen amikor a hangulatok ily módon az egészében vett létező elé vezetnek el bennünket, akkor rejtik el előlünk a Semmit, amelyet keresünk. Most még kevésbé lesz az a véleményünk, hogy a hangulatilag megnyilvánult egészében vett létezőnek a tagadása a Semmi elé állít bennünket. Ilyesmi megfelelő módon eredendően csak egy olyan hangulatban történhet, amely legsajátabb leleplezési értelme szerint a Semmit nyilvánítja meg.

Megtörténik-e az ember jelenvalólétében egy olyan hangoltság, melyben ő maga a Semmivel szembesül? Ez a történés csak pillanatokra lehetséges, és – jóllehet elég ritkán – valóságos is a szorongás alaphangulatában. A szorongásban – azt mondjuk – „otthontalannak érezzük magunkat”. Nem tudjuk megmondani, mitől otthontalan, valaki egészében érzi így magát. Minden dolog, mi magunk is, közömbösségbe süllyedünk. Az egészében vett létezőnek ez az elmozdulása, ami a szorongásban körülvesz bennünket, szorongat minket. Nem marad támaszunk. Ami marad és ami ránk tör – midőn a létező elsiklik – az ez a „nincs”. A szorongás megnyilvánítja a Semmit. A szorongásban az egészében vett létező talajtalanná válik. Milyen értelemben történik ez meg? Azt talán mégsem akarjuk állítani, hogy a szorongás megsemmisíti a létezőt, hogy ily módon meghagyja számunkra a Semmit. Hogyan is tehetné ezt, amikor a szorongás éppen az egészében vett létezővel szembeni tehetetlenségben találtatik.

A Semmi sajátosan a létezővel és a létezőn mint valami elsikló egészen mutatkozik meg, ezt a létezőt mint a teljességgel másikat nyilvánítja meg – a Semmivel szemben. Csak a szorongás Semmijének világos éjszakájában keletkezik a létező mint olyan eredendő nyitottsága: hogy az létező – és nem Semmi. De ez az általunk beszédünkben hozzámondott „és nem Semmi” nem valami járulékos magyarázat, hanem egyáltalán a létező megnyilvánulásának előzetes lehetővé tétele. Csak a Semmi eredendő megnyilvánulásának alapján képes az ember jelenvalóléte hozzáférni a létezőhöz és beléhatolni.

Jelenvalólét annyit tesz: beletartottság a Semmibe. A jelenvalólét, minthogy beletartja magát a Semmibe, már eleve túl van az egészében vett létezőn. Ezt a létezőn való túllétet nevezzük

transzcendenciának*. Ha a jelenvalólét létezése alapjában nem transzcendálna, s ez itt azt jelenti, hogy nem tartaná bele magát eleve a Semmibe, akkor sohasem viszonyulhatna a létezőhöz, tehát önmagához sem. A Semmi eredendő megnyilvánulása nélkül nincs Önmagalét és nincsen szabadság. A Semmi közvetlenül és többnyire a maga eredetiségében elleplezett a számunkra. Mi által van elleplezve? Azáltal, hogy meghatározott módon teljesen bele vagyunk veszve a létezőbe. Minél inkább a létező felé fordulunk tevés-vevésünk során, annál kevésbé hagyjuk azt mint olyant elsiklani, s annál inkább elfordulunk a Semmitől. S annál biztosabb, hogy a jelenvalólét nyilvános felszínére tolakszunk.

Mi tanúsítaná behatóbban a Semmi állandó és kiterjedt, bár elleplezett megnyilvánulását jelenvalólétünkben, mint a tagadás? A Semmi a tagadás eredete, nem pedig megfordítva. Ha pedig így a Semmire és a létre irányuló kérdezés mezején megtöretett az értelem hatalma, akkor ezzel eldőlt a „logika” sorsa is a filozófián belül. A „logika” eszméje feloldódik egy eredendőbb kérdezés örvényében.

A jelenvalólétnek a rejtett szorongás alapján való beletartottsága a Semmibe az egészében vett létező meghaladása: a transzcendencia. A Semmire irányuló kérdezésünk magát a metafizikát állítja elénk. A metafizika a létezőn túlra kérdez, méghozzá azért, hogy a létezőt mint olyant a maga egészében a megértés számára visszanyerje. A Semmi nem lesz többé a létező meghatározatlan szembenálló párja, hanem mint a létező létéhez tartozó lepleződik le. Mert maga a lét lényegében véges, és csak a Semmibe beletartott jelenvalólét transzendenciájában nyilvánul meg.

A tudományos jelenvalólét egyszerűsége és ereje abban áll, hogy kitüntetett módon viszonyul magához a létezőhöz és egyedül ahhoz viszonyul. A Semmit a tudomány egy fölényes gesztussal fel szeretné adni. Most azonban a Semmire vonatkozó kérdezésben világossá válik, hogy ez a tudományos jelenvalólét csak akkor lehetséges, ha eleve beletartja magát a Semmibe. Csak akkor érti meg magát abban, ami, ha nem – 68 – adja fel a Semmit. A tudomány állítólagos józansága és fölénye nevetségessé lesz, ha nem veszi komolyan a Semmit. Csak azért teheti a tudomány vizsgálódás tárgyává magát a létezőt, mert a Semmi megnyilvánul.

A létező a maga egész furcsaságában csak azért tör ránk, mert a létező alapjaiban a Semmi megnyilvánul. Csak ha gyötör bennünket a létező furcsasága, csak akkor ébreszti fel bennünk és vonja magára csodálkozásunkat. Csak a csodálkozás alapján – azaz a Semmi megnyilvánulásának az alapján – jön elő a „Miért?”. Az okokra bizonyos módon rákérdezni, s valamit megokolni csak azért tudunk, mert lehetséges a Miért mint olyan. S csak azért van egzisztenciánk kezébe adva a kutató sorsa, mert kérdezni és megokolni tudunk. A Semmire vonatkozó kérdés bennünket, a kérdezőket tesz kérdésessé. Ez metafizikai kérdés.

Az emberi jelenvalólét csak akkor tud létezőhöz viszonyulni, ha beletartja magát a Semmibe. A létezőn való túllépés a jelenvalólét létezésében történik meg. Ez a túllépés azonban maga a metafizika. Ebben a következő rejlik: a metafizika „az ember természetéhez” tartozik. Sem nem az iskolás filozófia egyik ága, sem pedig az önkényes ötletek mezeje. A metafizika az alaptörténés a jelenvalólétben. Amennyiben az ember egzisztál, bizonyos módon megtörténik a filozofálás. A filozófia a metafizika beindítása, az, amiben a metafizika eljut önmagához és kifejezett faladataihoz. A filozófia csak azáltal indul be, ha saját egzisztenciánk sajátlagos módon beugrik az egészében vett jelenvalólét alaplehetőségeibe. Ezen beugrás szempontjából a következő a döntő: először teret adni az egészében vett létezőnek; azután átengedni magunkat a Semminek, azaz megszabadulni azoktól a bálványoktól, amelyekkel mindenki rendelkezik, s amelyekhez oda szokott lopódzni; s végezetül hagyni, hogy szabadon lebegjünk, hogy állandóan visszalendüljünk a metafizika alapkérdéséhez, amely magát a Semmit kényszeríti ki: Miért van egyáltalán létező, nem pedig inkább Semmi?

Jegyzetek

egzisztencia – az ember mint önmegértő, véges létező

„van” – a magyar nyelv jelen idő 3. személyben nem

használja a létigei állítmányt

diszpozíció – Heidegger kifejezése: hangoltság, melyben

kifejeződik az ember világra való ráutaltsága

jelenvalólét – Heidegger kifejezése: emberi egzisztencia

transzcendencia – tapasztalat feletti

 

Másolat. Részletek. Forrás: az alábbi. A ténylegesen beszkennelt állapotban csak egy jelet javítottam 120 szöveghelyen ő-re.Cím eredeti írásmódban:

“FILOZÓFIAI

SZÖVEGGYŐJTEMÉNY”

EGYETEMI JEGYZET

Szerkesztette:

KOVÁCS ZOLTÁN

LISZT FERENC ZENEMŐVÉSZETI EGYETEM

2009

 

ISBN 978 963 7181 43 6

A KIADÁSÉRT FELELİS:

A LISZT FERENC ZENEMŐVÉSZETI EGYETEM REKTORA

PÉLDÁNYSZÁM: 100

NYOMDA: MESTERPRINT KFT., BUDAPEST

További Schopenhauer szövegek

További Schopenhauer szövegek: bővítő kiegészítések magyarul

1

Ami a halálban félelmes a számunkra,  semmiképp sem a fájdalom: mert ez, egyrészt, nyilvánvalóan a halálon innen  van, másrészt gyakran a fájdalomból menekülünk a halálba, csakúgy, ahogy  máskor meg épp fordítva, a legborzalmasabb fájdalmat is vállaljuk, hogy a  haláltól, bár az gyors volna s könnyű, még egy darabig menekedhessünk.  Különbséget teszünk tehát a fájdalom s a halál mint két merőben más rossz  közt: amitől a halálban félünk, az valójában az individuum bukása, s a halál  leplezetlenül meg is nyilvánul ilyenként, és mert az individuum maga az  életakarat az egyes egyedi objektivációban, egész lényege tiltakozik a halál  ellen. Ahol mármost az érzés ily menthetetlenül kiszolgáltat bennünket, közbeléphet az ész, s annak visszás benyomásait nagyrészt legyűrheti, magasabb  álláspontra helyezvén bennünket, ahol az egyedi egyes helyett most már az  általános (a mérvadó).

2

Annak bensőséges és csupán érzett tudata, amit  éppen oly világosan megismertünk az eddigiekben, jóllehet, mint mondtuk,  megakadályozza, hogy a halál gondolata már az ésszel élő lény életét is megmérgezhesse, hiszen az ily ép tudat mindamaz életkedv alapja, mely az élőt  derekasan fenntartja mind, és bátran élteti, mintha nem volna halál, addig  tudniillik, míg az életet tudja szeme előtt tartani, s tekintete erre irányul; nem  akadályozza meg azonban ez azt, hogy ha a halál egyes egyedileg s a valóságban, vagy esetleg akár csak a fantáziában is, megközelíti az individuumot, kinek  is akkor figyelembe kell vennie tényét, ne érezzen halálfélelmet az egyén, ne  akarjon menekülni minden módon. Mert ahogyan addig, míg megismerése az  életre mint olyanra irányult, s ebben a véghetetlenséget vélhette fölfedezni, így  most, hogy a halált látja, már ezt kell fölismernie. Hogy nem  érinti őt a halál, mely érinthetetlenség is mint magánvalónak lesz a része, a  jelenség számára ez az egyebekbeni külvilág további fennmaradásával esik  egybe.

3

Aki az emberi felfogásnak  ezt a sajátosságát valóban figyelembe veszi, be fogja látni, hogy ennek pszichológiai magyarázatai, melyek a szokásra és az elkerülhetetlenbe való belenyugvás tényére építenének, korántsem elégségesek, és a valódi ok az imént  megadott, mélyebben fekvő. Ugyanezen okból magyarázható az is, hogy minden korban, minden nép körében élnek dogmák az individuum valamiféle fennmaradásáról a halál után, s e tételek tiszteletnek is örvendenek, jóllehet a bizonyítékok megannyiszor igencsak szegényesek, az ellenkezőjére viszont  erősek és számosak, sőt ez utóbbihoz nem is kell külön bizonyíték, hiszen  lényegében a józan értelem ismeri el tényként a dolgot.

4

A jelen, tartalmával együtt, mindig itt van: mindkettő ingadozás  nélkül, szilárdan áll; mint a szivárvány a vízesés sugarán. Mert az akaratnak az  élet, az életnek a jelen biztos és bizonyos. Persze ha visszagondolunk az eltűnt  évezredekre, azokra az embermilliókra, akik ezek során éltek, megkérdezzük:  mik voltak ők? mivé lettek? De ha ugyanakkor épp csak a magunk életének  múltját idézzük fel ekképpen, ha jeleneteit képzeletünkben megelevenítjük, s  így kérdezzük megint: mi volt mindez? mivé lett ez? Ahogy ezzel, ugyanígy áll a  dolog ama milliók életével. Vagy vélekedjünk úgy, hogy a múlt avval, hogy a  halál ráütötte pecsétjét, új létezésre jut? Saját múltunk, már csak a legközelebbi  is, a tegnapi nap maga mindössze a fantázia semmis álma, és ugyanez mind  ama milliók múltja szintígy. Mi volt? Mi van? Az akarat, melynek tükre az élet,  és az akarattól szabadult megismerés. A múltban  senki ember még nem élt, és a jövőben sem fog élni, hanem a jelen minden élet  egyedüli formája, egyszersmind azonban biztos birtoka is, melyet senki el nem  vehet tőle.

5

Az idő  feltarthatatlan folyamhoz hasonlít, és a jelen mintha szikla lenne, amelyen e  folyam megtörik, de nem tudja elsodorni. Az akarat mint magánvaló ugyanúgy  nincs alávetve az ok elvének, mint a megismerés szubjektuma, mely végső  soron bizonyos szempontból mégis maga az akarat vagy az akarat megnyilvánulása; és ahogy az akaratnak az élet, saját jelensége, bizonyosság, ugyanígy  az a jelen is, a való élet egyetlen formája. Eszerint nem kell kutatnunk az élet  előtti múltat, sem a halál utáni jövőt: ellenkezőleg, épp azt az egyetlen formát  kell megismernünk, amelyikben az akarat megjelenik: a jelent; a jelen nem  szökhet meg az akarat elől, de az akarat sem a jelenből. Akit tehát az élet úgy,  ahogy van, kielégít, aki az életet minden módon igenli, az bízvást tekintheti  végtelennek is.

Schopenhauer excerpts

Schopenhauer  on life, birth and death

(Book Four, pp.355-358)

“Birth and death belong merely to the phenomenon of will, thus to life; and it is essential to this to exhibit itself in individuals which come into being and pass away, as fleeting phenomena appearing in the form of time phenomena of that which in itself knows no time, but must exhibit itself precisely in the way we have said, in order to objectify its peculiar nature. Birth and death belong in like manner to life, and hold the balance as reciprocal conditions of each other, or, if one likes the expression, as poles of the whole phenomenon of life. The wisest of all mythologies, the Indian, ex presses this by giving to the very god that symbolises destruction, death (as Brahma, the most sinful and the lowest god of the Trimurti, symbolises generation, coming into being, and Vishnu maintaining or preserving), by giving, I say, to Siva as an attribute not only the necklace of skulls, but also the lingam, the symbol of generation, which appears here as the counterpart of death, thus signifying that generation and death are essentially correlatives, which reciprocally neutralise and annul each other.

It was precisely the same sentiment that led the Greeks and Romans to adorn their costly sarcophagi, just as we see them now, with feasts, dances, marriages, the chase, fights of wild beasts, bacchanalians, &c.; thus with representations of the full ardour of life, which they place before us not only in such revels and sports, but also in sensual groups, and even go so far as to represent the sexual intercourse of satyrs and goats. Clearly the aim was to point in the most impressive manner away from the death of the mourned individual to the immortal life of nature, and thus to indicate, though without abstract knowledge, that the whole of nature is the phenomenon and also the fulfilment of the will to live. The form of…

(356 THE WORLD AS WILL. BK. iv.)

this phenomenon is time, space, and causality, and by means of these individuation, which carries with it that the individual must come into being and pass away. But this no more affects the will to live, of whose manifestation the individual is, as it were, only a particular example or specimen, than the death of an individual injures the whole of nature. For it is not the individual, but only the species that Nature cares for, and for the preservation of which she so earnestly strives, providing for it with the utmost prodigality through the vast surplus of the seed and the great strength of the fructifying im pulse. The individual, on the contrary, neither has nor can have any value for Nature, for her kingdom is infinite time and infinite space, and in these infinite multiplicity of possible individuals. Therefore she is always ready to let the individual fall, and hence it is not only exposed to destruction in a thousand ways by the most insignificant accident, but originally destined for it, and conducted towards it by Nature herself from the moment it has served its end of maintaining the species. Thus Nature naively expresses the great truth that only the Ideas, not the individuals, have, properly speaking, reality, i.e., are complete objectivity of the will. Now, since man is Nature itself, and indeed Nature at the highest grade of its self-consciousness, but Nature is only the objectified will to live, the man who has comprehended and retained this point of view may well console himself, when contemplating his own death and that of his friends, by turning his eyes to the immortal life of Nature, which he himself is. This is the significance of Siva with the lingam, and of those ancient sarcophagi with their pictures of plowing life, which say to the mourning beholder, Natura non contristatur.

That generation and death are to be regarded as some thing belonging to life, and essential to this phenomenon of the will, arises also from the fact that they both exhibit themselves merely as higher powers of the expres-…

(THE ASSERTION AND DENIAL OF THE WILL. 357 )

sion of that in which all the rest of life consists. This is through and through nothing else than the constant change of matter in the fixed permanence of form; and this is what constitutes the transitoriness of the individual and the permanence of the species. Constant nourishment and renewal differ from generation only in degree, and constant excretion differs only in degree from death. The first shows itself most simply and distinctly in the plant. The plant is throughout a constant recurrence of the same impulse of its simplest fibre, which groups itself into leaf and branch. It is a systematic aggregate of similar plants supporting each other, whose constant reproduction is its single impulse. It ascends to the full satisfaction of this tendency through the grades of its metamorphosis, finally to the blossom and fruit, that compendium of its existence and effort in which it now attains, by a short way, to that which is its single aim, and at a stroke produces a thousand-fold what, up till then, it effected only in the particular case the repetition of itself. Its earlier growth and development stands in the same relation to its fruit as writing stands to printing. With the animal it is clearly quite the same.

The process of nourishing is a constant reproduction; the process of reproduction is a higher power of nourishing. The pleasure which accompanies the act of procreation is a higher power of the agreeableness of the sense of life. On the other hand, excretion, the constant exhalation and throwing off of matter, is the same as that which, at a higher power, death, is the contrary of generation. And if here we are always content to retain the form without lamenting the discarded matter, we ought to bear ourselves in the same way if in death the same thing happens, in a higher degree and to the whole, as takes place daily and hourly in a partial manner in excretion: if we are indifferent to the one, we ought not to shrink from the other. | Therefore, from this point of view, it appears just as perverse to desire…

(358 THE WORLD AS WILL. BK . iv. )

the continuance of an individuality which will be replaced by other individuals as to desire the permanence of matter which will be replaced by other matter. It appears just as foolish to embalm the body as it would be carefully to preserve its excrement. As to the individual consciousness which is bound to the individual body, it is absolutely interrupted every day by sleep. Deep sleep is, while it lasts, in no way different from death, into which, in fact, it often passes continuously, as in the case of freezing to death. It differs only with regard to the future, the awaking. Death is a sleep in which individuality is forgotten; everything else wakes again, or rather never slept.

Above all things, we must distinctly recognise that the form of the phenomenon of will, the form of life or reality, is really only the present, not the future nor the past. The latter are only in the conception, exist only in the connection of knowledge, so far as it follows the principle of sufficient reason. No man has ever lived in the past, and none will live in the future; the present alone is the form of all life, and is its sure possession which can never be taken from it. The present always exists, together with its content. Both remain fixed without wavering, like the rainbow on the waterfall For life is firm and certain in the will, and the present is firm and certain in life. “

THE WORLD AS WILL AND REPRESENTATION BOOK FOUR

 

Existence, Kirkegaard, Sartre

Excerpts from “Either/Or”

“What is a poet? An unhappy person who conceals profound anguish in his heart but whose lips are so formed that as sighs and cries pass over them they sound like beautiful music. It is with him as with the poor wretches in Phalaris’s bronze bull, who were slowly tortured over a slow fire; their screams could not reach the tyrant’s ears to terrify him; to him they sounded like sweet music. And people crowd around the poet and say to him, “Sing again …

Kirkegaard

Either/Or

(From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia)

Either/Or portrays two life views. Each life view is written and represented by a fictional pseudonymous author, with the prose of the work reflecting and depending on the life view being discussed. For example, the aesthetic life view is written in short essay form, with poetic imagery and allusions, discussing aesthetic topics such as music, seduction, drama, and beauty. The ethical life view is written as two long letters, with a more argumentative and restrained prose, discussing moral responsibility, critical reflection, and marriage. The views of the book are not neatly summarized, but are expressed as lived experiences embodied by the pseudonymous authors. The book’s central concern is the primal question asked by Aristotle, “How should we live?”

The aesthetic is the personal, subjective realm of existence, where an individual lives and extracts pleasure from life only for his or her own sake. In this realm, one has the possibility of the highest as well as the lowest. The ethical, on the other hand, is the civic realm of existence, where one’s value and identity are judged and at times superseded by the objective world. In simple terms, one can choose either to remain oblivious to all that goes on in the world, or to become involved. More specifically, the ethic realm starts with a conscious effort to choose one’s life, with a choice to choose. Either way, however, an individual can go too far in these realms and lose sight of his or her true self. Only faith can rescue the individual from these two opposing realms. Either/Or concludes with a brief sermon hinting at the nature of the religious sphere of existence, which Kierkegaard spent most of his publishing career expounding upon. Ultimately, Kierkegaard’s challenge is for the reader to “discover a second face hidden behind the one you see” in him/herself first, and then in others.

Situation III

par Jean-Paul Sartre

Résumé

Situation III (dont le sous-titre est : « Lendemain de guerre »), est une œuvre de l’écrivain, dramaturge, et philosophe Français Jean Paul Sartre. C’est plus particulièrement un recueil de cinq articles publié en 1949 en France aux éditions Gallimard….

Sartre effectue son analyse à travers l’existentialisme et autour de l’être humain dont la race a été avilie et asservie, mais qui n’est pas sans espoir pour autant. Si l’individu a …

Sartre et l’existence

Sartre renverse la perspective classique depuis Platon, qui défend une approche essentialiste : l’essence précède l’existence, la philosophie se doit ainsi chez les Grecs et leurs successeurs d’étudier l’Etre. Ainsi, dans la République de Platon, l’existence n’est qu’un mode secondaire, dérivé de l’Etre.

Ek-sistere, chez Sartre, signifie se projeter hors de soi. L’homme existe en ce qu’il n’est rien de défini, il devient ce qu’il a décidé d’être. L’homme…

See More

crée son existence en se choisissant. La notion même de “nature humaine” est absurde, puisque cela confère à l’homme une essence à laquelle l’homme ne peut pas s’arracher (seuls les objets ont une nature, une fonction déterminée,

le sens de l’homme est de créer du nouveau, de modifier la figure du monde.L’homme vit pourtant mal cette situation de totale liberté. Il invente ainsi des subterfuges, notamment la mauvaise foi. La mauvaise foi consiste à faire semblant de croire que l’on est pas libre, c’est se rêver chose

L’homme fait de la facticité son excuse pour se faire en-soi. Sartre distingue 6 modes de facticité, c’est-à-dire de déterminations pesant sur l’homme :

le fait de naître dans une société et une époque donnée

le fait d’avoir un corps

le fait d’avoir un passé

le fait d’exister dans un monde qui nous préexiste

le fait d’exister parmi d’autres sujets (question de l’intersubjectivité)

le fait de mourir (finitude)

Pour Sartre, il faut assumer notre contingence.

( L’athéisme de Sartre est une exigence pour aller jusqu’au bout de la solitude de l’homme et sa responsabilité totale.)

Updated homepage incl. Russell Ch.V.

NB Ricoeur’s comment on Gurvitch (see below screenshots)

1 Comment

Károlyi Tibor 08/10-én írtad: ” Ezért is helyeztem el a l”existence című albumot valóságos tájakkal, növényekkel, állatokkal, házakkal, emberekkel.” Akkor az exisztencia-fogalmad Russellét követi? Szerinte viszont az univerziálék csak fennállnak (subsist), valók, habár azok is reálisak. Ebben is követed?

Földes Földes Miért ne? Nem szégyen az…

Károlyi Tibor Igenám, de régebben az elvont fogalmak realitását hangoztató “realisták” áramlata idealista volt, velük szemben a nominalistáknak volt igazuk.

Károly Nagy‎ to Földes Földes

“A szabadság témát a szociológus Gurvitch sokkal alaposabban dolgozta fel, mint a filozófus Sartre.” (aug 4.) Az lehet, de az általad legutóbb hivatkozott La Nausée részlet szociológiai leírásnak sem utolsó. Eszerint az önközpontú korlátoltságot nem menti egy altruista érték (szeretet) hangoztatása.

Comments

Erika Sass

Erika Sass “partnere tudatlanságát” Ehhez kapcsolom Károly Nagy megjegyzését az önközpontü korlátoltságról. Annak ellentéte a felvilágosult önérdek, amely másokra is tekintettel van és így végül maga is több előnyhöz jut, mint a pitiáner. Persze ehhez szélesebb látókör kell, ami állandó művelődést is feltételez.

Erika Sass “a megszokott szavakat a szeretetről” egy globális világnézeti hatalmi szervezet a maga létjogosultságának igazolására használja fel.

Boglár Széna Első kommentedhez: van egy harmadik, a saját előnyök szempontját kikerülni tudó megközelítés is:az emelkedett gondolkodású, nem aprólékoskodó, nagylelkű embereké. Akármilyen a szakmája és az anyagi helyzete, ez az igazi entellektüel.

Mimi Németh Az utóbbi szót tartsuk fenn a szellemi alkotások létrehozóira, kivéve a szűkagyú szakbarbárokat. Amit körvonalaztatok, azt régebben nemes magatartásnak nevezték.

Erika Sass‎ to Földes Földes

A legutóbb említett La Nausée-ben milyen megfigyelések, észrevételek érdemelnek különösebb figyelmet szerinted?

 

Földes Földes Erika Sass: Leírja a maga fejlődését, melynek eredménye “Egy ember, egész ember, akit minden emberből gyúrtak össze, aki valamennyivel felér, s akivel felér bármelyikük,” (1967.kiad., 161.l.) De a legnagyobb művének a La Nausée-t tartom.

Erika Sass‎ to Földes Földes

aug 4-i jegyzeted szerint Sartre “Bölcseletének szépírói alkotásai viszont nagyon tetszenek, például “A szavak”.

Mimi Németh‎ to Földes Földes

Az egyéni lényeg szabad megválasztását viszont helyeselted és a magadét honlapra helyezted. Kedvenc Gurvitchomból felraktam pár könyvoldal képet a saját Fb oldalamra.

Ferenc Kalas‎ to Földes Földes

Mimi Németh: készítettem róla egy nyersfordítást.

Földes Földes

July 16 ·

Excerpts from “Either/Or”

“What is a poet? An unhappy person who conceals profound anguish in his heart but whose lips are so formed that as sighs and cries pass over them they sound like beautiful music. It is with him as with the poor wretches in Phalaris’s bronze bull, who were slowly tortured over a slow fire; their screams could not reach the tyrant’s ears to terrify him; to him they sounded like sweet music. And people crowd around the poet and say to him, “Sing again …

Either/Or

(From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia)

Either/Or portrays two life views. Each life view is written and represented by a fictional pseudonymous author, with the prose of the work reflecting and depending on the life view being discussed. For example, the aesthetic life view is written in short essay form, with poetic imagery and allusions, discussing aesthetic topics such as music, seduction, drama, and beauty. The ethical life view is written as two long letters, with a more argumentative and restrained prose, discussing moral responsibility, critical reflection, and marriage. The views of the book are not neatly summarized, but are expressed as lived experiences embodied by the pseudonymous authors. The book’s central concern is the primal question asked by Aristotle, “How should we live?”

The aesthetic is the personal, subjective realm of existence, where an individual lives and extracts pleasure from life only for his or her own sake. In this realm, one has the possibility of the highest as well as the lowest. The ethical, on the other hand, is the civic realm of existence, where one’s value and identity are judged and at times superseded by the objective world. In simple terms, one can choose either to remain oblivious to all that goes on in the world, or to become involved. More specifically, the ethic realm starts with a conscious effort to choose one’s life, with a choice to choose. Either way, however, an individual can go too far in these realms and lose sight of his or her true self. Only faith can rescue the individual from these two opposing realms. Either/Or concludes with a brief sermon hinting at the nature of the religious sphere of existence, which Kierkegaard spent most of his publishing career expounding upon. Ultimately, Kierkegaard’s challenge is for the reader to “discover a second face hidden behind the one you see” in him/herself first, and then in others.

Situation III

par Jean-Paul Sartre

Résumé

Situation III (dont le sous-titre est : « Lendemain de guerre »), est une œuvre de l’écrivain, dramaturge, et philosophe Français Jean Paul Sartre. C’est plus particulièrement un recueil de cinq articles publié en 1949 en France aux éditions Gallimard….

Sartre effectue son analyse à travers l’existentialisme et autour de l’être humain dont la race a été avilie et asservie, mais qui n’est pas sans espoir pour autant. Si l’individu a …

Sartre et l’existence

Sartre renverse la perspective classique depuis Platon, qui défend une approche essentialiste : l’essence précède l’existence, la philosophie se doit ainsi chez les Grecs et leurs successeurs d’étudier l’Etre. Ainsi, dans la République de Platon, l’existence n’est qu’un mode secondaire, dérivé de l’Etre.

Ek-sistere, chez Sartre, signifie se projeter hors de soi. L’homme existe en ce qu’il n’est rien de défini, il devient ce qu’il a décidé d’être. L’homme crée son existence en se choisissant. La notion même de “nature humaine” est absurde, puisque cela confère à l’homme une essence à laquelle l’homme ne peut pas s’arracher (seuls les objets ont une nature, une fonction déterminée,

le sens de l’homme est de créer du nouveau, de modifier la figure du monde.L’homme vit pourtant mal cette situation de totale liberté. Il invente ainsi des subterfuges, notamment la mauvaise foi. La mauvaise foi consiste à faire semblant de croire que l’on est pas libre, c’est se rêver chose

L’homme fait de la facticité son excuse pour se faire en-soi. Sartre distingue 6 modes de facticité, c’est-à-dire de déterminations pesant sur l’homme :

le fait de naître dans une société et une époque donnée

le fait d’avoir un corps

le fait d’avoir un passé

le fait d’exister dans un monde qui nous préexiste

le fait d’exister parmi d’autres sujets (question de l’intersubjectivité)

le fait de mourir (finitude)

Pour Sartre, il faut assumer notre contingence.

( L’athéisme de Sartre est une exigence pour aller jusqu’au bout de la solitude de l’homme et sa responsabilité totale.)

1Ala Cojocaru

Like

(Sartre et la liberté)

«L’être ne saurait engendrer que l’être et, si l’homme est englobé dans ce processus de génération, il ne sortira de lui que de l’être. S’il doit pouvoir interroger sur ce processus, c’est-à-dire le mettre en question, il faut qu’il puisse le tenir sous sa vue comme un ensemble, c’est-à-dire se mettre lui-même en dehors de l’être et du même coup affaiblir la structure d’être de l’être. Toutefois il n’est pas donné à la “réalité humaine” d’anéantir, même…

See More

L’humanistes par Sartre

(La Nausée)

(Text sans accent grave, circonflex, cédille, etc.)

…L’humaniste radical est tout particulierement l’ami des

fonctionnaires. L’humaniste dit «de gauche» a pour

souci principal de garder les valeurs humaines; il n’est

d’aucun parti, parce qu’il ne veut pas trahir l’humain, mais

ses sympathies vont aux humbles; c’est aux humbles qu’il

consacre sa belle culture classique. C’est en general un

veuf qui a l’ceil beau et toujours embué de larmes; il

pleure aux anniversaires. II aime aussi le chat, le chien,

tous les mammifdres supérieurs. L’écrivain communiste

aime les hommes depuis le deuxieme plan quinquennal;

il chatie parce qu’il aime. Pudique, comme tous les forts,

il sait cacher ses sentiments, mais il sait aussi, par un

regard, une inflexion de sa voix, faire pressentir, derriere

ses rudes paroles de justicier, sa passion apre et douce

pour ses freres. L’humaniste catholique, le tard-venu, le

benjamin, parle des hommes avec un air merveilleux. Quel

beau conte de fées, dit-il, que la plus humble des vies, celle

d’un docker londonien, d’une piqueuse de bottines! II a

choisi humanisme des anges; il écrit, pour l’edification

des anges, de longs romans tristes et beaux, qui obtiennent

fréquemment le prix Fémina.

Ca, ce sont les grands premiers roles. Mais il y en a

d’autres, une nuée d’autres : le philosophe humaniste,

qui se penche sur ses freres comme un frere ainé et qui a le

sens de ses responsabilites; l’humaniste qui aime les

hommes tels qu’ils sont, celui qui les aime tels qu’ils

devraient etre, celui qui veut les sauver avec leur agrement

et celui qui les sauvera malgré eux, celui qui veut créer

des mythes nouveaux et celui qui se contente des anciens, ,

celui qui aime dans 1’homme sa mort, celui qui aime dans

l’homme sa vie, l’humaniste joyeux, qui a toujours le

mot pour rire, l’humaniste sombre, qu’on rencontre sur-

tout aux veillées funebres. Ils se haissent tous entre eux :

en tant qu’individus, naturellement — pas en tant

qu’hommes. …

— Peut-etre que vous etes misanthrope?

Je sais ce que dissimule ce fallacieux effort de concilia-

tion. Il me demande peu de chose, en somme : simplement

d’accepter une Etiquette. Mais c’est un piege : si je consens

l’Autodidacte triomphe, je suis aussitot tourné, ressaisi,

depassé car l’humanisme reprend et fond ensemble toutes

les attitudes humaines. Si l’on s’oppose a lui de front, on

fait son jeu; il vit de ses contraires. Il est une race de gens

tétus et bornés, de brigands, qui perdent a tout coup contre

lui : toutes leurs violences, leurs pires exces, il les digere,

il en fait une lymphe blanche et mousseuse. II a digeré

l’anti-intellectualisme, le manichéisme, le mysticisme, le

pessimisme, l’anarchisme, l’égotisme : ce ne sont plus

que des étapes, des pensées incompletes qui ne trouvent

leur justification qu’en lui. La misanthropie aussi tient sa

place dans ce concert : elle n’est qu’une dissonance néces-

saire a l’armonie du tout. Le misanthrope est homme :

il faut done bien que l’humaniste soit misanthrope en

quelque mesure. Mais c’est un misanthrope scientifique,

qui a su doser sa haine, qui ne hait d’abord les hommes

que pour mieux pouvoir ensuite les aimer.

Je ne veux pas qu’on m’integre, ni que mon beau sang

rouge aille engraisser cette bete lymphatique : je ne

commettrai pas la sottise de me dire « anti-humaniste ».

Je ne suis pas humaniste, voila tout.

— Je trouve, dis-je a l’Autodidacte, qu’on ne peut pas

plus hair les hommes que les aimer.

L’Autodidacte me regarde d’un air protecteur et loin-

tain. Il murmure, comme s’il ne prenait pas garde a ses

paroles :

— II faut les aimer, il faut les aimer…

— Qui faut-il aimer? Les gens qui sont ici?

— Ceux-la aussi. Tous.

II se retourne vers le couple a la radieuse jeunesse :

voila ce qu’il faut aimer. Il contemple un moment le

monsieur aux cheveux blancs. Puis il ramene son regard

sur moi; je lis sur son visage une interrogation muette.

Je fais « non » de la tete. II a 1’air de me prendre en pitié.

— Vous non plus, lui dis-je agacé, vous ne les aimez

pas.

— Vraiment, monsieur? Est-ce que vous me permettez

d’avoir un avis different?

II est redevenu respectueux jusqu’au bout des ongles,

mais il fait l’ceil ironique de quelqu’un qui s’amuse énor-

m^ment. II me hait. J’aurais eu bien tort de m’attendrir

sur ce maniaque. Je l’interroge a mon tour :

— Alors, ces deux jeunes gens, derriere vous, vous les

aimez?

II les regarde encore, il réfléchit :

— Vous voulez me faire dire, reprend-il soupconneux,

que je les aime sans les connaitre. Eh bien, monsieur,

je l’avoue, je ne les connais pas,.. A moins, justement, que

l’amour ne soit la vraie connaissance, ajouta-t-il avec un

rire fat.

— Mais qu ‘est-ce que vous aimez?

— Je vois qu’ils sont jeunes et c’est la jeunesse que

j’aime en eux. Entre autres choses, monsieur.

II s’interrompit et preta l’oreille

— Est-ce que vous comprenez ce qu’ils disent?

Si je comprends! Le jeune homme, enhardi par la sym-

pathie qui l’entoure, raconte, d’une voix pleine, un match

de football que son equipe a gagné l’an dernier contre un

club havrais.

— Il lui raconte une histoire, dis-je a l’Autodidacte.

— Ah! Je n’entends pas bien. Mais j’entends les voix,

la voix douce, la voix grave : elles alternent. C’est… c’est

si sympathique.

— Seulement moi, j’entends aussi ce qu’ils disent, mal-

heureusement.

— Eh bien?

— Eh bien, ils jouent la comédie.

— Véritablement? La comedie de la jeunesse, peut-

etre? demande-t-il avec ironie. Vous me permettez, mon-

sieur, de la trouver bien profitable. Est-ce qu’il sufiit de la

jouer pour revenir a leur age?

Je reste sourd a son ironie; je poursuis :

— Vous leur tournez le dos, ce qu’ils disent vous

échappe… De quelle couleur sont les cheveux de la jeune

femme?

Il se trouble :

— Eh bien, je… — il coule un regard vers les jeunes

gens et reprend son assurance — noirs!

— Vous voyez bien!

— Comment?

— Vous voyez bien que vous ne les aimez pas, ces

deux-la. Vous ne sauriez peut-etre pas les reconnaitre dans

la rue. Ce ne sont que des symboles, pour vous. Ce n’est

pas du tout sur eux que vous etes en train de vous atten-

drir; vous vous attendrissez sur la Jeunesse de l’Homme,

sur l’Amour de l’Homme et de la Femme, sur la Voix

humaine.

— Eh bien? Est-ce que ca n’existe pas?

— Certes non, ca n’existe pas! Ni la Jeunesse ni l’Age

mur, ni la Vieillesse, ni la Mort…

Le visage de 1’Autodidacte, jaune et dur comme un coing,

s’est figé dans un tetanos reprobateur. Je poursuis nean-

moins :

— C’est comme ce vieux monsieur derriere vous, qui

boit de Feau de Vichy. C’est l’Homme mur, je suppose,

que vous aimez en lui; l’Homme mur qui s’achemine avec

courage vers son declin et qui soigne sa mise parce qu’il

ne veut pas se laisser aller?

— Exactement, me dit-il avec defi.

— Et vous ne voyez pas que c’est un salaud?

II rit, il me trouve étourdi, il jette un bref coup d’oeil

sur le beau visage encadré de cheveux blancs :

— Mais, monsieur, en admettant qu’il paraisse ce que

vous dites, comment pouvez-vous juger cet homme sur sa

mine? Un visage, monsieur, ne dit rien quand il est au

repos.

Aveugles humanistes! Ce visage est si parlant, si net —

mais jamais leur ame tendre et abstraite ne s’est laisse

toucher par le sens d’un visage.

— Comment pouvez-vous, dit l’Autodidacte, arreter

un homme, dire il est ceci ou cela? Qui peut épuiser un

homme? Qui peut connaitre les ressources d’un homme?

Épuiser un homme! Je salue au passage 1’humanisme

catholique a qui l’Autodidacte a emprunté, sans le savoir,

cette formule.

— Je sais, lui dis-je, je sais que tous les hommes sont

admirables. Vous etes admirable. Je suis admirable. En

tant que créatures de Dieu, naturellement.

II me regarda sans comprendre, puis avec un mince

sourire :

— Vous plaisantez sans doute, monsieur, mais il est

vrai que tous les hommes ont droit a notre admira-

tion. C’est difficile, monsieur, tres difficile d’etre un

homme.

II a quitté sans s’en apercevoir 1’amour des hommes

en Christ; il hoche la tete et, par un curieux phenomene

de mimétisme, il ressemble a ce pauvre Guéhenno,

— Excusez-moi, lui dis-je, mais alors je ne suis pas

bien sur d’etre un homme : je n’avais jamais trouvé ca

bien difficile. II me semblait qu’on n’avait qu’a se laisser

aller.

L’Autodidacte rit franchement, mais ses yeux restent

mauvais :

— Vous etes trop modeste, monsieur. Pour supporter

votre condition, la condition humaine, vous avez besoin,

comme tout le monde, de beaucoup de courage. Monsieur,

1’instant qui vient peut etre celui de votre mort, vous le

savez et vous pouvez sourire : voyons! n’est-ce pas admi-

rable? Dans la plus insignifiante de vos actions, ajoute-t-il

avec aigreur, il y a une immensity d’heroisme.

— Et comme dessert, messieurs? dit la bonne.

L’Autodidacte est tout blanc, ses paupieres sont bais-

sees a demi sur des yeux de pierre. II fait un faible geste

de la main, comme pour m’inviter a choisir.

— Un fromage, dis-je avec heroisme.

— Et monsieur?

II sursaute.

— Hé? Ah! oui : eh bien, je ne prendrai rien, j’ai fini.

— Louise!

Les deux gros hommes paient et s’en vont. Il y en un

qui boite. Le patron les reconduit a la porte : ce sont des

clients d’importance, on leur a servi une bouteille de vin

dans un seau a glace.

Je contemple l’Autodidacte avec un peu de remords :

il s’est complu toute la semaine a imaginer ce dejeuner,

ou il pourrait faire part a un autre homme de son amour

des hommes. II a si rarement l’occasion de parler. Et

voila : je lui ai gaché son plaisir. Au fond il est aussi seul

que moi; personne ne se soucie de lui. Seulement il ne se

rend pas compte de sa solitude. Eb bien, oui : mais ce

n’était pas a moi de lui ouvrir les yeux. Je me sens tres

mal a l’aise : je rage, c’est vrai, mais pas contre lui, contre

les Virgan et les autres, tous ceux qui ont empoisonné

cette pauvre cervelle. Si je pouvais les tenir la, devant moi,

j’aurais tant a leur dire. A l’Autodidacte, je ne dirai rien,

je n’ai pour lui que de la sympathie : c’est quelqu’un dans

le genre de M. Achille, quelqu’un de mon bord, qui a

trahi par ignorance, par bonne volonté!

Like

L’humanisme existentialiste

L’existentialisme est un humanisme

Jean-Paul Sartre

 …

“On m’a reproché de demander si l’existentialisme était un humanisme. On m’a dit : mais vous avez écrit dans La Nausée que les humanistes avaient tort, vous vous êtes moqué d’un certain type d’humanisme, pourquoi y revenir à présent ? En réalité, le mot humanisme a deux sens très différents. Par humanisme on peut entendre une théorie qui prend l’homme comme fin et comme valeur supérieure.

Mais il y a un autre sens de l’humanisme, qui signifie au fond ceci : l’homme est constamment hors de lui-même, c’est en se projetant et en se perdant hors de lui qu’il fait exister l’homme et, d’autre part, c’est en poursuivant des buts transcendants qu’il peut exister ; l’homme étant ce dépassement et ne saisissant les objets que par rapport à ce dépassement, est au cœur, au centre de ce dépassement. Il n’y a pas d’autre univers qu’un univers humain, l’univers de la subjectivité humaine. Cette liaison de la transcendance, comme constitutive de l’homme – non pas au sens où Dieu est transcendant, mais au sens de dépassement -, et de la subjectivité, au sens où l’homme n’est pas enfermé en lui-même mais présent toujours dans un univers humain, c’est ce que nous appelons l’humanisme existentialiste. Humanisme, parce que nous rappelons à l’homme qu’il n’y a d’autre législateur que lui-même, et que c’est dans le délaissement qu’il décidera de lui-même ; et parce que nous montrons que ça n’est pas en se retournant vers lui, mais toujours en cherchant hors de lui un but qui est telle libération, telle réalisation particulière, que l’homme se réalisera précisément comme humain.

On voit, d’après ces quelques réflexions, que rien n’est plus injuste que les objections qu’on nous fait. L’existentialisme n’est pas autre chose qu’un effort pour tirer toutes les conséquences d’une position athée cohérente. Il ne cherche pas du tout à plonger l’homme dans le désespoir. Mais si l’on appelle comme les chrétiens, désespoir, toute attitude d’incroyance, il part du désespoir originel.

L’existentialisme n’est pas tellement un athéisme au sens où il s’épuiserait à démontrer que Dieu n’existe pas. Il déclare plutôt : même si Dieu existait, ça ne changerait rien ; voilà notre point de vue. Non pas que nous croyions que Dieu existe, mais nous pensons que le problème n’est pas celui de son existence ; il faut que l’homme se retrouve lui-même et se persuade que rien ne peut le sauver de lui-même, fût-ce une preuve valable de l’existence de Dieu. En ce sens, l’existentialisme est un optimisme, une doctrine d’action, et c’est seulement par mauvaise foi que, confondant leur propre désespoir avec le nôtre, les chrétiens peuvent nous appeler désespérés.”